In probability theory and statistics, a stochastic order quantifies the concept of one random variable being "bigger" than another. These are usually partial orders, so that one random variable may be neither stochastically greater than, less than, nor equal to another random variable . Many different orders exist, which have different applications.

Usual stochastic order

edit

A real random variable   is less than a random variable   in the "usual stochastic order" if

 

where   denotes the probability of an event. This is sometimes denoted   or  .

If additionally   for some  , then   is stochastically strictly less than  , sometimes denoted  . In decision theory, under this circumstance, B is said to be first-order stochastically dominant over A.

Characterizations

edit

The following rules describe situations when one random variable is stochastically less than or equal to another. Strict version of some of these rules also exist.

  1.   if and only if for all non-decreasing functions  ,  .
  2. If   is non-decreasing and   then  
  3. If   is increasing in each variable and   and   are independent sets of random variables with   for each  , then   and in particular   Moreover, the  th order statistics satisfy  .
  4. If two sequences of random variables   and  , with   for all   each converge in distribution, then their limits satisfy  .
  5. If  ,   and   are random variables such that   and   for all   and   such that  , then  .

Other properties

edit

If   and   then   (the random variables are equal in distribution).

Stochastic dominance

edit

Stochastic dominance relations are a family of stochastic orderings used in decision theory:[1]

  • Zeroth-order stochastic dominance:   if and only if   for all realizations of these random variables and   for at least one realization.
  • First-order stochastic dominance:   if and only if   for all   and there exists   such that  .
  • Second-order stochastic dominance:   if and only if   for all  , with strict inequality at some  .

There also exist higher-order notions of stochastic dominance. With the definitions above, we have  .

Multivariate stochastic order

edit

An  -valued random variable   is less than an  -valued random variable   in the "usual stochastic order" if

 

Other types of multivariate stochastic orders exist. For instance the upper and lower orthant order which are similar to the usual one-dimensional stochastic order.   is said to be smaller than   in upper orthant order if

 

and   is smaller than   in lower orthant order if[2]

 

All three order types also have integral representations, that is for a particular order   is smaller than   if and only if   for all   in a class of functions  .[3]   is then called generator of the respective order.

Other dominance orders

edit

The following stochastic orders are useful in the theory of random social choice. They are used to compare the outcomes of random social choice functions, in order to check them for efficiency or other desirable criteria.[4] The dominance orders below are ordered from the most conservative to the least conservative. They are exemplified on random variables over the finite support {30,20,10}.

Deterministic dominance, denoted  , means that every possible outcome of   is at least as good as every possible outcome of  : for all x < y,  . In other words:  . For example,  .

Bilinear dominance, denoted  , means that, for every possible outcome, the probability that   yields the better one and   yields the worse one is at least as large as the probability the other way around: for all x<y,   For example,  .

Stochastic dominance (already mentioned above), denoted  , means that, for every possible outcome x, the probability that   yields at least x is at least as large as the probability that   yields at least x: for all x,  . For example,  .

Pairwise-comparison dominance, denoted  , means that the probability that that   yields a better outcome than   is larger than the other way around:  . For example,  .

Downward-lexicographic dominance, denoted  , means that   has a larger probability than   of returning the best outcome, or both   and   have the same probability to return the best outcome but   has a larger probability than   of returning the second-best best outcome, etc. Upward-lexicographic dominance is defined analogously based on the probability to return the worst outcomes. See lexicographic dominance.

Other stochastic orders

edit

Hazard rate order

edit

The hazard rate of a non-negative random variable   with absolutely continuous distribution function   and density function   is defined as

 

Given two non-negative variables   and   with absolutely continuous distribution   and  , and with hazard rate functions   and  , respectively,   is said to be smaller than   in the hazard rate order (denoted as  ) if

  for all  ,

or equivalently if

  is decreasing in  .

Likelihood ratio order

edit

Let   and   two continuous (or discrete) random variables with densities (or discrete densities)   and  , respectively, so that   increases in   over the union of the supports of   and  ; in this case,   is smaller than   in the likelihood ratio order ( ).

Variability orders

edit

If two variables have the same mean, they can still be compared by how "spread out" their distributions are. This is captured to a limited extent by the variance, but more fully by a range of stochastic orders.[citation needed]

Convex order

edit

Convex order is a special kind of variability order. Under the convex ordering,   is less than   if and only if for all convex  ,  .

Laplace transform order

edit

Laplace transform order compares both size and variability of two random variables. Similar to convex order, Laplace transform order is established by comparing the expectation of a function of the random variable where the function is from a special class:  . This makes the Laplace transform order an integral stochastic order with the generator set given by the function set defined above with   a positive real number.

Realizable monotonicity

edit

Considering a family of probability distributions   on partially ordered space   indexed with   (where   is another partially ordered space, the concept of complete or realizable monotonicity may be defined. It means, there exists a family of random variables   on the same probability space, such that the distribution of   is   and   almost surely whenever  . It means the existence of a monotone coupling. See[5]

See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ Perrakis, Stylianos (2019). Stochastic Dominance Option Pricing. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-11590-6_1. ISBN 978-3-030-11589-0.
  2. ^ Definition 2.3 in Thibaut Lux, Antonin Papapantoleon: "Improved Fréchet-Hoeffding bounds for d-copulas and applications in model-free finance." Annals of Applied Probability 27, 3633-3671, 2017
  3. ^ Alfred Müller, Dietrich Stoyan: Comparison methods for stochastic models and risks. Wiley, Chichester 2002, ISBN 0-471-49446-1, S. 2.
  4. ^ Felix Brandt (2017-10-26). "Roling the Dice: Recent Results in Probabilistic Social Choice". In Endriss, Ulle (ed.). Trends in Computational Social Choice. Lulu.com. ISBN 978-1-326-91209-3.
  5. ^ Stochastic Monotonicity and Realizable Monotonicity James Allen Fill and Motoya Machida, The Annals of Probability, Vol. 29, No. 2 (April, 2001), pp. 938–978, Published by: Institute of Mathematical Statistics, Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2691998

Bibliography

edit
  • M. Shaked and J. G. Shanthikumar, Stochastic Orders and their Applications, Associated Press, 1994.
  • E. L. Lehmann. Ordered families of distributions. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 26:399–419, 1955.